The prism through which every nation looks at the outside world has been shaped by
its own experience. For a policy-maker, there is as much truth in Eliot's "Hell is
ourselves" as in Sartre's "L'enjer, c'est les autres." How the same challenge (say
decolonization) is met by France or Britain tells us much more about the domestic
values and political habits of each nation than about the particular external circumstances that distinguish the French from the British problem. Any study of foreign
policy that sets goals which cannot be reached so long as the nation does not change
its skin and its soul is of limited worth. ---- Hoffmann, 1965 |
Expanded Contents | Figures | Tables 1. Perspective And Summary 15A. Phasing Propositions and Their Evidence on International Conflict Vol. 1: The Dynamic Psychological Field
Democratic Peace page |
I could stop here in my analysis, for expectations and dispositions provide insight into behavior, are measurable,
This clearly will not do, for a full understanding of international relations and conflict requires engaging power, ideology, perception, distance, situation, and the like. Such factors or forces must underlie expectations and dispositions; they must be brought out and their relationship to behavior clearly shown. Much unpacking must be done.
This I did at the conceptual level in Vol. 1: The Dynamic Psychological Field and Vol. 2: The Conflict Helix. In Vol. 1: The Dynamic Psychological Field I argued that the dynamic psychological field has a tetradic structure: expectations, behavioral dispositions, personality, and situation. An understanding of the relationship between these aspects provide insight into a person's behavior. In Vol. 2: The Conflict Helix I focused this tetradic structure on the social behavior of one person to another, and argued that it takes place in a perceived situation and relative to the sociocultural distances (which include status and class) between actor and object: situation weights distances. And these distances reflect the personality
Because international relations are social relations among individuals (albeit in different authoritative and individual capacities), the analysis of Vol. 2: The Conflict Helix applies here. Understanding international behavior and conflict means bringing in situation and distances. But in doing so, an approach different from Vol. 2: The Conflict Helix must be taken. For there the concern was conceptual and philosophical, and social and psychological understanding. I could ignore precise distinctions, methodological problems, and express only very general equations. Measurement was not of concern, insight was.
Here, however, both understanding and measurement are involved. I have the dual purpose of explaining behavior and rigorously defining this explanation with practical equations. I am after insight and meaningful numbers.
These aims create a double burden. I must be more logically discriminating and rigorous than before, but I must tie this logic into an intuitively meaningful explanation. I have tried to do this in the previous Chapters (e.g., Chapter 5), but within the logical framework defined in Vol. 1: The Dynamic Psychological Field and Vol. 2: The Conflict Helix. Now, the framework itself must be extended. To do this, I will begin by focusing on an actor's behavior in a situation as perceived uniquely by him.
Now, this aggregate is of common expectations and dispositions, of common structures and processes of conflict. The aggregate reflects general international patterns among all actors. And this common level would suffice, if our concern were only with expectations, dispositions, and behavior.
But I am also interested in the underlying field forces--the distances. To focus on these forces toward behavior we must move down to the individual level--to that of an actor in a situation as he perceives it. For while the field forces, such as status and class distances, are common across actors, each actor will be influenced by them in his own way.
An aggregate measure of behavior will amalgamate such different situations. The total threats of an actor to another over some period, for example, may well be due to one situation or be a combination of many. For this reason we should subdivide common behavior h,ij into that specific to each situation. To wit:
Equation 6.1:
- h,ij = ghg,ij ,
- where
- g = a situation;
- g= the summation across situations 1,2,3, . . . , g, . . . .
That is, the common behavior of an actor i to another, such as its total threats, is an aggregate of behavior within separate situations 1,2, . . . , g, . . . , as i perceives them. And within each situation distinct common behavior hg,ij can be defined. Thus, we can consider, say, the number of threats of Brezhnev to Carter in an arms control situation distinct from those he makes in reaction to Carter's emphasis on human rights.
Now, i's behavior in a situation is subject to the same analysis as made of overall behavior. It is a composite of expectations and behavioral dispositions, except that since the situation is as i perceives it, the expectations will be specific to i as well. Thus,
Equation 6.2:
- hg,ij = higwg,ij,
- where
- wg,ij = actor i's behavioral disposition toward j in situation g;
- hig = i's expectation of the outcome of behavior h in situation g.
And from Equations 6.1 and 6.2,
Equation 6.3:
- h,ij = ghigwg,ij
It should be clear that common expectations hk and dispositions in Equation 5.1 and hig and wg,ij in the above are not the same. Both are expectations weighting dispositions; both sum to the same common behavior. One, however, is shared expectations among actors weighting dispositions reflecting common structures of expectations and conflict processes; the other is actor specific situational expectations and dispositions.
The expectations hk shared by all actors and the situational expectations hig of an actor are not independent. Each shared expectation is a complex result of the interaction between an actor's situational expectations and dispositions.
The rules of the road provide our everyday example. Each of us may see our automobile differently and we use it within our own perceived situations--to get to work, to shop, to display status, to conduct business, to make go to the beach. Each of us will have individual expectations and dispositions regarding our car. But on the road we all have developed shared expectations about the rules of the road--about signalling turns, stop lights, passing, and so on. These common expectations enable us to achieve our situational expectations.
Similarly, transactions involve a general structure of expectation among states, or rules, contracts, norms, and the like. However, this structure is an outcome of each actor's specific situational expectations. For the United States, for example, transactions may be the outcome of a philosophy of free trade, a general belief in cooperative interactions and the benefits of an open market. Thus, a multitude of transactions reflect the diverse decisions of private individuals and groups seeking to gratify their own interests. However, for the Soviet Union, transactions may be fully determined by the elite, who see them as a factor in the historical struggle between capitalism and socialism, and particularly, the need for Western trade to overcome Soviet economic deficiencies. Still, these different situational expectations can lead, and have for the United States and Soviet Union, to shared expectations governing transactions. Thus, one could look at actual U.S.-Soviet transactions as a result of these shared expectations and common dispositions, or as of the situational expectations and dispositions.
To summarize this Section, common, overall behavior is an aggregate of behavior in different, actor-perceived situations. And behavior in a situation is a product of situational expectations and behavioral dispositions.
Equation 6.4:
- wg,ij = kgikwk,ij,
- where
- wk,ij = the common dispositions of Equation 5.1;
- gik = i's expectation of the outcome of behavior wk,ij in situation g.
An actor's situational disposition is a composite of his common dispositions weighted by his expectations of the outcome of these common dispositions in a particular situation.
But now we have two kinds of situational expectations. Those relating a specific behavior to situational disposition, and those relating situation to common dispositions. These can be put into one equation. From Equation 6.2 and Equation 6.4,
Equation 6.5:
- hg,ij = hig(kgikwk,ij).
Then, from Equation 6.1,
Equation 6.6:
- h,ij = g(kgikwk,ij).
This last equation now shows how aggregate common behavior is divided into the two kinds of situational expectations: those relating to specific behavior h and situational disposition; those relating situation and dispositions.
For example, the equation means that the number of Carter's threats to China is a result of the expectations Carter has of the outcome of threats in each situation he perceives between China and the United States (such as the Sino-Soviet conflict, the danger to South Korea from the North, the stability of Southeast Asia, the Taiwan problem in normalizing U.S.-China relations); and these expectations weight his disposition to behave towards China in a certain way in each situation. Moreover, these situational dispositions themselves result from Carter's expectation of the outcome in each situation weighting his common dispositions toward China--the common structures of expectations and conflict processes between the United States and China.
Equations 6.1 to 6.6 focus on the variation in the common behavior of an actor, and define this variation as dependent upon his perceived situation, as reflected in his situational expectations and dispositions. Figure 6.1 delineates this variation and its elements for an actor.
As for Figure 5.3, the variation of interest is defined in Figure 6.1 by vector notation:
The situational expectations hig and gik are scalar parameters.
The equation at the bottom of Figure 6.1 is the vector counterpart of scalar Equation 6.6;
Finally, there is the question as to how the behavioral space-time of an actor fits into the overall international space-time of all actors, as pictured in Figure 5.4. Figure 6.3 illustrates that in dealing with an actor alone, I am not defining a new space-time, but only a region of the space-time of all actors. Thus, the matrix of i's common behavior, i, is a submatrix of ,
I have argued that in each situation an actor perceives, he is disposed to behave towards another in a certain way. And that this situational, behavioral disposition is a combination of his common dispositions weighted by expectations of the outcomes within the situation. Moreover, I have argued that the actual common behavior of an actor towards another is a combination of the situational dispositions weighted by expectations of the behavioral outcome.
* Scanned from Chapter 6 in R.J. Rummel, War, Power, Peace, 1979. For full reference to the book and the list of its contents in hypertext, click book. Typographical errors have been corrected, clarifications added, and style updated.. I see no need to include these functions here.2. Such have been done, for example, in my Field Theory Evolving (1977: Chapter 5).
3. Personality involves temperament and personal abilities, to be sure, but also attitudes, interests, needs, sentiments, values, cognitive structures, and roles. See Vol. 1: The Dynamic Psychological Field.
4. I am here arguing for Model II of field theory (Rummel, 1977: especially Section 4.4 and Chapter 16). Model I presumes that common forces operate in the same way for all actors. Although I discarded this for Model II before empirically testing the field theory equations, some "let's see what would happen anyway" empirical assessment of Model I was done using distance vectors. The results showed no better ability to predict behavior overall than guesswork. That is, assuming actors are similarly influenced by underlying field forces (in terms of differences) provides no general ability to predict behavior. Model II is later stated as Actor Proposition 16.7 in Appendix 16.B.
When Model I is used as a framework for linking dyadic behavior to the actors' attributes and absolute or squared distances, however, some moderate relationships do appear. See, for example, Appendix I, Section 4.
5. From the previous equations and those to follow, the explicit functions can be worked out. They are complex, involving summations, products and quotients of situational expectations and dispositions Wk
6. The vector equation is written in statistical notation for clarity. Introducing vector algebra at this point would only add another layer of symbols (e.g., the vector of parameters gi) to no manipulative end.
7. Technically, the common behavioral space-time of actors is first determined through common factor analysis. Then that portion of the common space-time defining i's behavior is used in subsequent analyses of situational expectations and dispositions. This is done through employing only i's common behavior dispositions (factor scores on the components of common space-time). On these technical terms, see "Understanding Factor Analysis".
The importance of this approach is that i's common behavior is defined relative to that behavior of other actor's; i's behavior is explained within the common behavioral field. Thus, context is maintained and the results explain not only why i made more threats to object j, than to k, but also why i made more threats than, say, agreements, with object j in comparison to the behavior of other actors to j.
8. All this is consolidated into the Actor Proposition 16.7 in Appendix 16B, which the systematic evidence presented there strongly supports.