Other Democratic Peace Documents On This SiteWhat is the "democratic peace"? "Waging denuclearization and social justice through democracy" "The rule of law: towards eliminating war" "Freedom of the press--A Way to Global Peace" Bibliography on Democracy and War Q & A On Democracies Not Making War on Each Other "The democratic peace: a new idea?" "Libertarianism, Violence Within States, and the Polarity Principle" "Democracies ARE less warlike than other regimes" Vol. 2: The Conflict Helix (see Chapter 35) Vol. 4: War, Power, Peace (see e.g., Propositions 16.11 and 16.27 |
ABSTRACT
Based on theory and previous results, three hypotheses are posed:
These hypotheses are statistically tested against scaled data on all reported international conflict for 1976 to 1980; and where appropriate, against a list of wars from 1816 to 1974, and of threats and use of force from 1945 to 1965. The three hypotheses are found highly significant. Tests were also made for contiguity as an intervening variable and were negative. Finally, two definitions of "libertarian" are tested, one involving civil liberties plus political rights, the other adding in economic freedom. Both are highly positive, but economic freedom is also found to make a significant added reduction in the level of violence for a state overall or between particular states.
- Libertarian states have no violence between themselves.
- The more libertarian two states, the less their mutual violence.
- The more libertarian a state, the less its foreign violence.
My purpose here is to test this conclusion directly against the occurrence of conflict and violence for all states for the five years, from 1976 to 1980, and for all interstate wars since 1816.
At a more basic theoretical level, libertarian states comprise social fields in which the actions of groups and individuals respond to many divergent and opposing social and psychological forces. These forces spontaneously resolve into interlocking and nested balances of powers and associated structures of expectations. These define the social order. Such systems (like the free market) tend to be self-regulating and to isolate and inhibit conflicts and violence when they occur. They tend to encourage exchange, rather than coercive and violent solutions, in conflict between groups and individuals.
Libertarian states are by theory not only less violence prone, but when foreign relations includes the perception of other libertarian states, this inhibition becomes a mutual barrier to violence. Their mutual domestic diversity and pluralism, their free and competitive press, their people-to-people and elite-to-elite bonds and relationships, and their mutual identification and sympathy will foreclose on any expectation or occurrence of war between them; violence may occur only in the most extraordinary and unusual circumstances, or at the margins of what it means to be libertarian.
In sum, there are two propositions implied, one relating to interstate violence, the other to the overall violence of a state (operational statement in parentheses):
As to systematic evidence for the first Proposition, a survey of the literature uncovered fourteen relevant empirical studies. Ten support (three strongly) it and three are negative.
In evaluating this evidence, including that to be presented here, keep in mind the unusual nature of this proposition. It is not a statement of correlation, association, or relationship. It is an absolute (or "point') assertion: There will be no violence between libertarian states. One clear case of violence or war unqualified by very unusual or mitigating circumstances falsifies the proposition.
As for the Freedom Proposition, the evidence in the literature described in Rummel (Vol. 4: War, Power, Peace) is mixed but tends to support it. Of 25 relevant studies, 13 favor (4 strongly) the proposition and 10 are opposed (6 strongly). However, when only directly relevant studies are considered, those in favor number the same, while those that oppose the proposition drop to 8 (with 5 strongly negative). Finally, if only important studies (covering large historical periods, large samples, or many variables) are counted, 6 are positive (4 strongly), while only 3 are opposed (one strongly). The result is that the more directly relevant and important the published study, the more likely its findings will support the proposition.
Freedom is best measured by the degree to which governmental power is decentralized and limited and society is based on exchange. Here it suffices to measure the level of economic freedom (from governmental ownership, control, and regulation). Thus the two definitions are:
The Freedom House publication Freedom at Issue presents annually a 7-point scale of all states on their political rights and civil liberties.
Freedom at Issue also classifies states by their economic and political systems (see Wright, 1982, for a useful refinement of the economic classification). According to my estimate of the economic freedom under each subclassification, I distributed scale values 1 through 14 in the following manner:
Freedom is then measured as the scale values for political freedom plus those for economic freedom, which gives equal weight to political and economic freedom. Thus freedom for Belgium in 1977 equals 2 + 1 = 3; for Sweden 2 + 9 = 11; for Senegal 8 + 9 = 17; for Poland 11 + 9 = 20; and for East Germany 14 + 14 = 28.
I need also to group states and dyads by their degree of libertarianism and to keep distinct the two definitions of a libertarian state. The most objective way of doing this is to divide the political freedom and freedom scales into the types listed in Table 1. These scales and types are now the basic data on libertarianism for testing the propositions.
In application to the event data, each variable (with one exception) is scaled from 1 to 8 by judging the hostility involved, severity of underlying conflict, values, and stakes at issue, and the possibility of escalation to more intense conflict, including violence and war. The full definitions cannot be given here, but, for example, the
- warnings-and-threats variable is scaled as
- 0 = none;
- 4 = warning or threat of hostilities short of war, or warning or threat of significant negative sanctions;
- 8 = ultimatum (or threat of war).
- The economic sanctions variable is scaled
- 0 = none;
- 2 = politically significant, showing coolness of relations;
- 4 = politically significant, showing cold and somewhat antagonistic relations (or part of coercive diplomacy); and 8 = severe sanctions (or strongest possible economic sanctions outside of boycott, embargo, or blockade).
- The alert variable is scaled as
- 0 = none;
- 2 = politically significant expectations of military action and low, simple preparation for a contingency;
- 4 = an alert preparing for likely military action but of lesser magnitude than a war alert;
- 8 = an alert threatening or involved in preparations for war (or complete and highest alert possible).
- And the war variable is scaled as
- 0 = none,
- 1 = a minor, limited war fought in a remote area, or a declaration of war or statement of war involvement without much military action following;
- 2 = border war, high intensity, but clearly limited to the border,
- 4 = war, but not fought totally (if lost, revolutionary domestic change not threatened);
- 8 = a total war, from the state's perspective (or revolutionary domestic change threatened by a loss).
The number killed scale needs to be given completely. It is
- 0 = none killed in official dyadic violence;
- 1 = 1 to 5 killed;
- 2 = 6 to 25 killed;
- 3 = 26 to 225;
- 4 = 226 to 1,125;
- 5 = 1,126 to 5,625;
- 6 = 5626 to 28,125;
- 7 = 28,126 to 140,625;
- 8 = 140,626 to 703,125;
- 9 => 703,125.
Where this is roughly a logarithmic (to the base 5) scale selected and, adjusted to index the step-up in political intensity with increased casualties, and to give scale values comparable to those for other variables.
I tested the reliability of the above scaling procedures on 1,500 news reports involving 37 dyads and 24 states. The independent scalings of two untrained volunteers were compared to that used here. The t-test of the difference between the mean scalings for each variable was nonsignificant (p <.73; .70); the product-moment correlations
The dyad profiles across the seventeen variables need to be collapsed into one scale of nonviolent conflict/ violence/war. Figure 1 presents a Scaling Transformation Chart for the seventeen conflict variables. The scale values of a variable were aligned from left to right in the chart according to the underlying intensity of conflict, in comparison to the scale values of the other variables. Thus it can be seen that the scale values of the accusations variable are usually to the left of the same values for the protests variable; values for protests are to the left of the same ones for threats and warnings. And considering the dimensionality of the groups of variables as one moves from negative communications variables at the top to the military action variables at the bottom, the scale values for the variables move to the right. Actually, as a result, the Foreign Conflict Scale of Figure 1 is roughly divisible into left to right segments, corresponding to these dimensions, as shown at the bottom. One can convert from a variable scale value to the Foreign Conflict Scale as follows:
The selected, symmetrical dyads listed in Table 2 provide examples; for each a Foreign Conflict Scale value is shown. For India and Pakistan this is determined by referring to its profile in Figure 1, where the value of 4 for the accusations variable has the highest (is furthest to the right) Foreign Conflict Scale value, 10. For the Iran-Iraq dyad, both war and number killed variables give the same maximum Foreign Conflict Scale value of 47. Such Foreign Conflict Scale values for 1980, as well as those for the other dyads, are the conflict data for the tests to be conducted here.
Reliability tests were done on the Foreign Conflict Scale using the event data scalings independently generated for the assessment described above. There was no significant mean-scale difference from the final scale scores used here (p <.92; 98);
Overall, then, this approach to measuring conflict produces one ordinal scale measuring the intensity of conflict with clear demarcations between violent and nonviolent conflict and between war and nonwar.
More important, the Foreign Conflict Scale helps to overcome data bias and unavailability. Because of interest and a free press, data are more easily available on the low-level conflicts of Western and open societies. As conflicts become more intense they tend to be reported, even for totalitarian states. The invasion of Afghanistan by the USSR could not be hidden, but a sanction against North Korea by China would likely be unknown outside their elite circles unless publicized for propaganda purposes. To sum weighted or unweighted counts across conflict variables therefore biases the resulting scale downward for closed (such as Albania), remote (such as Gambia), and uninteresting (such as Rwanda) states. My scale helps to avoid this, since the more intense an action, the more likely it is that it will be reported, and one clash between, say Albania and Yugoslavia, is sufficient to place this dyad above any other without violence, irrespective of their negative sanctions or communications.
Finally, the Foreign Conflict Scale is appropriate and conservative in testing the propositions of concern here, since both focus on the occurrence of violence. Rightly, then, any one act of violence or of war automatically creates a high Foreign Conflict Scale value, whereas no matter how many negative communications or sanctions, the Foreign Conflict Scale value will be low or moderate.
Table 3 lists the wars and campaigns of violence (the systematic use of violence for political ends) reflected by the Foreign Conflict Scale values of Figure 1 for the 1976-1980 period. Not shown are the many violent incidents, involving a singular confrontation, clash, or attack, that also are scaled. For other purposes, some of these incidents might be omitted, such as the firing by Iranian soldiers on the ships of Panama and Japan caught in the Shatt al Arab waterway when the Iran-Iraq war broke out. Such were included in the scaling so that any occurrence of violence between free states, however minor, could be caught.
Data were coded for all legally sovereign and independent states, and for all directed, interstate dyads for the years January 1, 1976, to December 31, 1980.
By nature of the propositions to be tested, directed dyad data (e.g., U.S. threats against Cuba) were converted to symmetrical dyad data (e.g., the threats between the United States and Cuba).
Hypothesis 1: Libertarian states have no violence between them.
Recall that "libertarian" is alternatively measured as political freedom or freedom. "Violence" means official violence, i.e., that between or involving government forces (the Soviet-Afghan war is an exception; see Note b to Table 3). This in mind, Table 4 presents the relevant theoretical and empirical frequencies.
Focusing on the frequencies for all cases, by Hypothesis 1 the expected (theoretical) frequency of violence is zero. And empirically there is no instance of violence between politically free or free states. Thus Hypothesis 1 is not falsified.
This lack of falsification may be only a lucky result. One way of testing for this is to consider the probability that the theoretical and empirical frequencies would be as close (or closer) than they are, were they truly from separate distributions. To test for this, consider the following null hypothesis.
Null Hypothesis 1: Libertarian states have violence between them.
This may be tested using the goodness-of-fit chi-square (
However, the chi-square goodness-of-fit test is problematic here because of the expected zero violence--even for large samples the theoretical expectations should be at least 5 for 1 d.f. to avoid misjudging the Null Hypothesis, although the very small p seems safe enough. An alternative without this problem is the binomial test. Let each case of violence equal a "success," each P-P (or F-F) dyad per year be a "trial," and the empirical probability of violence for each dyad for each year be the number of cases of violence divided by the total sample, or 121/ 62,040 = .00195. Also let the Null Hypothesis be that P-P (or FF) dyads are as likely to have at least as much violence as are other dyads. Then, for the P-P (or F-F) dyads the probability of zero violence for 3,530 (or 1,690) trials is .001 (or .037). Since both binomial tests are significant, this test also enables us to reject (for the Null Hypothesis) the possibility that chance explains the zero violence for P-P (or F-F) dyads.
In their article on the war-proneness of democracies, Small and Singer (1976) tested the belief that democracies are more peaceful than are other states.
Table 4 also presents the cases of violence for contiguous P-P and F-F dyads. Of course, since this is a subsample, we will also find zero violence as expected. However, the question here also is whether this is a random result, especially since the sample size is so much smaller than the one for all cases. If chance can explain the zero violence for contiguous libertarian states, this would suggest that the significant zero violence for all libertarian states is really due to their lack of common borders. As for the all-case sample, the goodness-of-fit chi-square test for the contiguous cases is zero at 1 d.f.; p <.005. The hypothesis of chance should be rejected.
The binomial test should also be applied here, especially because of the zero expected values. Defining "success" and "trials" and the Null Hypothesis as before, and the probability of success as 86/1,164 = .074, the binomial distribution gives the probability of zero violence for P-P contiguous states as p <.0003, and for F-F states as p <.018. For both meanings of libertarianism, therefore, and with both chi-square and binomial tests, we can prudently reject the hypothesis that the significant results for all cases are due to the lack of contiguity among libertarian states.
Such are the direct tests of Hypothesis 1. The conclusion is that it cannot be rejected by virtue of a negative case, and that it is highly unlikely that this lack of any violence is due to chance or to the lack of borders between libertarian states.
While Hypothesis 1 asserts an amount (zero) and not a correlation or association between libertarianism and violence, the credibility of the hypothesis will be increased if we also find that violence between states scales upward the less they are libertarian. This is because the underlying theory implies that there is a gradient of restraining effects on the intensity of foreign violence correlated with the degree of libertarianism within a state. We would surely be troubled if libertarian and partially libertarian states are more violent toward one another than are wholly nonlibertarian states, or if nonlibertarian states are, next to the libertarian ones, the least violent toward one another.
The tests to be presented for the Freedom Proposition (below) will give positive evidence for this gradient. Here it should suffice to show this. The percentage of dyads of each type with violence or war, moving through the six types of dyads from P-P (or F-F) to those involving the least libertarian NP-NP (or NF-NF), for the 1976-1980 period is shown in Table 5. Note that the last three types include no politically free (or free) states at all and have the highest percentage of violence; the last type has the highest of all. These percentages can be correlated with the level of libertarianism in a dyad. Let P (or F) = 0, PP (or PF) = 1, and NP (or NF) = 2. Then give a dyad type the joint score of its members as shown in Table 5. The resulting product-moment correlations between the decreasing libertarianism in the dyad and the percentage of violence are given at the end of Table 5, along with their significance. Clearly, decreasing libertarianism means increasing violence.
The violence for political freedom and freedom samples is plotted in Figure 2 and Figure 3. They show violence obviously scaling upward to the right, as we would expect from the above correlation. Especially important is that, for both plots, the best-fitting function (compared to power, logarithmic, and linear functions) is an exponential, or growth, curve. It bends upward toward higher violence as libertarianism decreases; as libertarianism increases it declines and crosses the violence threshold into nonviolence in the region of libertarian dyads. Although indirect, these plots and functions are among the most important results of this study. They show the great power of the underlying theory.
The growth functions for the above plots are fitted to the variance for all cases of violence, and the coefficient of determination (R2) is therefore not itself an indirect test. Only the direction and shape of the curve are. R2 is an appropriate indirect test, however, for the maximum violence reached for each scale value of political freedom or freedom. This will indicate the extreme range of violence likely per decrease in libertarianism and can be plotted in Figure 2 and Figure 3 by connecting the highest points reached for each freedom value.
Figure 4 shows the best-fitting curves to these maxima. For political freedom, a growth curve is still best, accounting for 85% of the variance (p <.4 x 10-52). This is strong, indirect support for Hypothesis 1. For freedom, the best fit is a power curve, reflecting the bunching of several wars among the middle freedom values in Figure 3; but it still moves upward even for the lowest nonlibertarian values. The R2 is also very highly significant, accounting for 43% of the variance (p <.4 x 10-20).
Not only violence, but if the underlying libertarian theory is correct, war also should increase with decreasing libertarianism in the dyad. We do find this for the 1976-1980 period, as can be seen from Table 5. The least libertarian states had the highest percentage of wars, and the correlation between a dyad's lack of political freedom (or freedom) and percentage of war is .81 (.74), both significant.
Note also from Figure 2 and Figure 3 that wars do not occur even near the region of Politically Free or Free dyads. For example, while a scale value of 8 is the threshold for political freedom, the dyads with war that are closest to it have a value of 24. This is, of course, consistent with the gradient we are testing for here, and which can be seen so well in the right triangular shape of the plots in Figure 2, and to a lesser extent, in Figure 3.
This result for war is so important that I have tried to broaden the sample beyond that used here. I have already mentioned the Small and Singer (1976) list of 50 interstate wars between 1816 and 1965. Table 6 presents the total number of dyads engaged in these wars from 1816 to 1918, the end of World War 1, and from 1919 to 1965. Overall, 325 dyads were involved in these wars, but with only the 11 marginal exceptions, they included no democracies fighting other democracies. This is true even though Small and Singer used a less restrictive definition for democracy than I did for libertarianism, which includes not only having the franchise and an effective legislature, but many additional civil liberties and political rights. Unfortunately, I do not have the data to determine the number of democracies in the world for the 1816-1965 period, and so the significance of the distribution in Table 6 cannot be tested. This aside, the distribution gives considerable indirect, subjective weight to Hypothesis 1.
Bueno de Mesquita (1981: 209) updated the Small and Singer list of wars to 1974. No democracies, as Small and Singer defined them, on the updated list had war. Considering my list of wars (from 1976 to 1980) in Table 2, the Small-Singer-Bueno de Mesquita list (from 1816 to 1974), and the fact that no war between democracies occurred in 1975 (and including the marginal exceptions noted above) we have not had a real war between democracies in over a century and a half, from 1816 to 1980.This gives more indirect, subjective support to Hypothesis 1.
Pride (1970) provides a classification of 14 democracies in terms of a democratization index and the stability of this index for the twentieth century. This gives us a very conservative (some of the democracies were marginally so, and lasted for only a few decades) way of testing the significance of the Small-Singer list of wars, as shown in Table 7. Clearly, using Prides sample of democracies, there has been a significant lack of war between them.
What about this possibility being due to the lack of borders between democracies? The number of dyads with and without war who share borders is also shown in Table 7. Unfortunately, because of the very low expected values for the top row of the table and the marginal values for the significance of the resulting chi-square, we cannot base a clear decision about the significance of this distribution on it. In this case, then, we can use the binomial test, which gives us a significance of p <.03 (one-tailed).
In sum, whether controlling for borders or not, the lack of wars between democracies is unlikely to have occurred by chance, and Hypothesis 1 is indirectly supported.
By theory we should expect not only a gradient of violence with decreasing libertarianism, but also that libertarian states make no preparations for violence or war regarding each other--the undefended border between the United States and Canada should be paradigmatic of libertarian states.
This point is also important methodologically. It may be that, tests for chance aside, the 1976-1980 period just happened to have no violence between libertarian states, but later periods will. If we find even no preparations for war or violence, even no activity warning of violence or war (such as shows of strength, alerts, troop movements) between libertarian states, the probability decreases that, relevant to Hypothesis 1, 1976-1980 is an aberrant sample of violence.
As will be shown for the Freedom Proposition (below) there are no warning and defensive acts between politically free or free states for the 1976-1980 period. Interestingly, when the maximum conflict behavior for each value of the Political Freedom or Freedom Scale is plotted, the best-fitting plots are logarithmic, dipping sharply down below violence and toward zero at the greatest freedom. This is shown in Figure 5 (to be clear, the difference between Figure 4 and Figure 5 is that in the former the functions fit only the maximum violence; in the latter the functions fit the maximum conflict behavior, violence or not, for each value of the libertarian scale). Relevantly, both curves decline steeply into the region of libertarian dyads at the threshold of warning and defensive acts.
As for war, it is important to determine whether other periods will also indirectly support this gradient extending to the threat of, or preparation for, violence. Table 8 presents 20 years of data on conflicts involving the threat or actual use of force. As shown, there were no such conflicts between democratic states, as defined by Feierabend and Feierabend (1972, 1973). And this is highly significant (p <.004), even when controlling for common borders (p <.027). This is a critical result, although indirect. It uses the definitions and data of others to arrive at the same conclusion as Hypothesis 1. The only reason the results must be considered indirect, however, is that threats of force were also involved, and such threats are not specifically part of the hypothesis.
H2: The more libertarian a state, the less its foreign violence.
H3: The more libertarian two states, the less their mutual foreign violence.
The first is a restatement of the operational expression of the proposition at the national level; the second states the proposition's implied operational meaning for dyadic relations. While obviously related, these hypotheses are separate and make distinct assertions about freedom.
As for the previous tests, "libertarian" will be alternatively defined here as political freedom (which comprises political rights and civil liberties) and freedom (which also includes economic freedom--a free market). Moreover, recall that by theory freedom is the preferred definition, since it defines the maximum freedom within a state; it is, indeed, what libertarians (or classical liberals) usually mean by freedom. Where possible, tests will be performed for any significant differences in results between the two definitions.
The first, which I will call the Max Violence Sample (N = 112), will consist of the maximum conflict behavior of each state between 1976 and 1980. This will avoid weighting the tests by the several states involved in continuous violence for the five years. These data, then, really will gauge the relationship between libertarian freedom and the highest intensity of conflict behavior reached during this period.
The second sample will comprise all cases of violence for each year, summed over the five years. Thus, if state i had a Conflict Scale value (as defined earlier regarding Figure 1) of 12 in 1976, 41 in 1977, and 21 in 1980, each of these values is a separate case (for the Max Conflict Sample, only the 41 in 1977 for state i would have been included). I will call this the Full Sample (N = 334). Although separate years with violence for the same state are thus considered different cases, this should not create a problem of dependent cases. Theoretically and mathematically, there is no necessary relationship between nonviolence in one year and violence or nonviolence in the previous or following year: Two states may be at peace one year, at war the next, and at peace the year after, or peace or war may extend over many years. Of course, there may be a temporal correlation in the occurrence of violence that can influence the tests. But this may work for or against the hypotheses, and there is no reason by theory that it should go either way. In any case, the Max Violence Sample does not have this problem and thus serves as a check for those who remain concerned about possibly dependent cases.
Table 9 presents the two samples, cross-classified by political freedom and freedom types, and the range of conflict behavior. The tabulated numbers are frequencies. To be sure the table is clear, for the Max Conflict Sample over the 1976-1980 period, only one politically free state (P) had conflict behavior no more intense than negative communications; four other politically free states had conflict behavior as intense as warning and defensive acts; and another politically free state was involved in a war. For the Full Sample and nonpolitically free (NP) states, there were a total of 32 cases of states having conflict behavior reaching the level of negative sanctions over the five years, i.e., [(number of NP states reaching the level of negative sanctions for 1976) + (those for 1977) + . . . + (those for 1980) = 32]. Now for Hypothesis 2.
The hypothesis first asserts a negative relationship between the libertarianism of states and their foreign violence. Table 9 gives the appropriate frequencies; the relationship between libertarianism and violence can be seen to be largely negative (the major exception being the nonwar violence for F cases in the Max Sample). However, the differences in these frequencies may be due simply to there being fewer P or F cases to have violence, for example. Table 10, therefore, presents the proportion of cases with violence. As can easily be seen, the proportions are in the hypothesized direction, and the correlations at the bottom of the table measure this (they are positive because the higher number for the nation type, the less libertarian it is). The correlations by themselves, or their significance, are not a sufficient test of Hypothesis 2, however; they are linear measures, while the relationship specified in Hypothesis 2 may be nonlinear.
The appropriate tests are provided in Table 11. Given (see above) that the data show the hypothesized direction of relationship, the question the table should answer is whether this is a significant contingency. Can we, with fair confidence, reject the possibility that these data favor Hypothesis 2 by chance? First, the Null Hypothesis.
Null Hypothesis 2: Violence is not less the freer a state (violence is either greater the more libertarian a state, or is independent of its libertarianism).
To reject this null hypothesis requires that the contingency table show a negative relationship between violence and libertarianism and that this be significant. The appropriate coefficient is the chi-square (
First, the contingency is in the opposite direction to that specified in the null hypothesis, as shown in Table 10. Second, all the
Is freedom a significantly better fit to the hypothesis than political freedom? Clearly, both definitions yield significant results. And the
If the theory underlying the hypothesis is valid, we also would expect that the more libertarian states are, the less they have wars. The data support this, significantly. The appropriate contingency table (like Table 11, with war in place of violence) can be calculated from Table 9 and Table 10, and would yield four
By theory, we also would expect that, relative to their nonviolent conflict behavior, the more libertarian states are, the less their violence. This is because the very forces that limit violence--greater activity among divergent interest groups, the greater pluralistic dynamism of open societies, the greater segmentation of interests, and the greater cross-pressures--also promote internal and external (nonviolent) conflict. This can be tested by cross-tabulating nonviolent conflict behavior and violence separately against the nation types for both samples. The contingencies would be then in the proper direction; the four
Second, this symmetrical dyadic data will be organized by year, so that the frequency counts will be of the number of dyads with given conflict behavior per year, over the five years. This is comparable to the Full Sample used above. A Max Sample is not employed because of the greater refinement in cross-classifications (for example, now instead of just a classification for free states F, there are F-F, F-PF, and F-NF subclassifications of dyads), and thus a reduction in subsample sizes (and expected values for a contingency table).
Third, since the hypothesis posits a general relationship between freedom and violence, one should avoid letting a dyad with violence over the five years and having the same joint political freedom or freedom score skew the tests. The conservative approach to the hypothesis, given that the test of Hypothesis 2 already shows a tendency for violence to be associated with nonlibertarian states, is to omit those years of data for a dyad for which the dyad's joint political freedom or freedom score is duplicated, keeping only the year of highest conflict behavior. This will combine the virtues of both the Full and Max Samples used above and make any positive results for Hypothesis 3 more robust. That is, it is a conservative procedure.
To make sure this procedure is understood, consider the data on violence for Ethiopia-Somalia. For those years having conflict behavior between these states, joint political freedom scores and Conflict Scale values of Figure 1 were for the years 1977, 1978, 1979, and 1980 respectively:
Joint Political Freedom: 28, 28, 28, 28;
Conflict Scale Value: 49, 47, 45, 45.
Therefore, since the joint PF were the same for these four years, only the data for the highest Conflict Scale value of Figure 1, which is for 1977, will be used. Had 1976 had conflict behavior, but with a different joint-PF score, it would have been also included. The year 1976, however, will be a case of no violence.
In total, 680 symmetrical dyads had conflict behavior over the five years 1976-1980 (that is, those dyads with conflict behavior in 1976 + those in 1977 + . . . + those in 1980 = 680). The sample for political freedom, omitting all but the highest conflict data for a dyad base whose joint political freedom scores were duplicated, is 510; for freedom it is 527. Therefore, the elimination procedure drops 23% to 25% of the cases.
Table 12 presents the data, subdivided as finely as the frequencies permit. These will be the basic data for testing the Hypothesis 3. Table 13 shows the hypothesis-relevant data on violence that were omitted.
One can see from Table 12 that there is a tendency overall for the raw frequency of violence to increase as joint political freedom and freedom decrease (note the clustering of zero violence in the upper right). This is even more obvious in Figure 2 and Figure 3, which plot this violence for the joint political freedom and freedom scores. To measure this increase in violence here, Table 14 gives the proportion of violence to total dyads. As for Hypothesis 2, the problem now is to determine the probability that the direction of relationship those proportions show and the contingencies also given in Table 14 are due to chance.
The Null Hypothesis to be tested is:
Null Hypothesis 3: Violence is not less between two states the more libertarian they are (violence is either greater between two states the more libertarian they are, or is independent of their libertarianism).
The correlation coefficients in Table 14 show the contingencies to be in the wrong direction for the null hypothesis; the
Are my data elimination procedures responsible for rejecting the null hypothesis? The answer can be seen in Table 13, in which the elimination of data on violence associated with duplicate political freedom or freedom scores tends to favor those dyads involving the least libertarian states (empirically they tend to have stable scores while also having the most violence, as for example, Vietnam; the freest states also tend to have stable scores, but with little violence), which would work for the null hypothesis. To prove this, I recalculated the
Freedom, as it should by theory, clearly does better in rejecting the null hypothesis than does political freedom, and the difference is highly significant.
For the Hypothesis 1, I tested the possibility that lack of common
borders between libertarian states may be causing the significant results.
This may also be true here. Table 15, therefore, presents the violence
data of Table 14 only for those dyads whose members are contiguous. If
the increase in violence with the decrease in libertarianism is due to
contiguity--it may be that the least libertarian states commonly share
borders, while the most libertarian have few--then the distribution of
violence in Table 15 should not enable us to reject Null Hypothesis 3.
However, as the proportions show and correlations measure, the
direction of relationship between violence and dyad type is opposite to
that specified by the Null Hypothesis; and the
Also as shown in Table 15, freedom still is the significantly better definition: Economic freedom does make a difference, even when controlling for contiguity.
There is another kind of direct test of Null Hypothesis 3, but this time using curvilinear regression. If the null hypothesis is correct, we should find anywhere from a horizontal line fitting a plot of violence against joint political freedom or freedom to a curve of decreasing violence with decreasing joint political freedom or freedom. The best regression curves among the linear, logarithmic, power, and exponential types are shown in Figure 2 and Figure 3. For political freedom and freedom these curves are:
- y = 28.9e.014x1
- R2 = .28 p <.6 x 10-11, one-tailed
- y = 31.3e.005x2
- R2 = .21 p <.6 x 10-7, one-tailed
- where
- y = violence score on the Conflict Scale of Figure 1
- x1 = joint dyadic political freedom score
- x2 = joint dyadic freedom score
- R2 = coefficient of determination
- N = 121 (see Note 16)
For both political freedom and freedom these are growth curves that cross the violence threshold beyond the region of jointly free dyads and curve upward in violence as the dyad's joint freedom declines. This contradicts Null Hypothesis 3, and, judging by the R2, very significantly so. Therefore, for this kind of test also, alternative Hypothesis 3 must be accepted.
So far, only the central tendency of violence, which was found to lie along the above curves, has been tested. However, if Hypothesis 3 is correct, we would also expect that the peak violence would increase with decreasing political freedom or freedom scores. Since the curvilinear test for the central tendency was based on minimizing the squared deviations from the curve (i.e., least squares regression analysis), it is possible for the peak violence (defined by the top points in the plots, as shown in Figure 2 and Figure 3) to remain the same or even decrease with decreasing libertarianism, inconsistent with Hypothesis 3. Were either to occur it would question the hypothesis, regardless of the central tendency. Therefore, a regression analysis was done on the highest level of violence reached for each scale value of political freedom (N = 19) and for transformed scale values
The best-fitting regression curves (among linear, logarithmic, power, and exponential) for these maximum intensity data are these:
- y = 25.97e.025x1
- R2 = .85 p <.2 x 10-7, one-tailed
- y = 18.3e.3x2
- R2 = .53 p <.0002, one-tailed
- where
- y = maximum violence (Conflict Scale value of Figure 1) reached by any dyad
- x1 = joint dyadic political freedom score
- x2 = joint dyadic freedom score
- N1 = 19
- N2 = 20
Both curves are plotted in Figure 4. Note that these curves are of different types. The one for political freedom is a growth curve, with the maximum violence between states curving upward as their joint political freedom decreases; the other is a power curve, which has its greatest slope upward in maximum violence between states when they are partially free. Because of the jump in magnitudes of violence in the middle ranges of freedom, the curve crosses the violence threshold just within the region of jointly free dyads in spite of their having no violence. Moreover, the difference between these curves shows that the decrease in civil liberties and political rights increases the intensity of violence most when they are all but eliminated. But the added decrease in economic freedom increases the intensity of violence most at the early or middle stages--that is, when free market economies become mixed socialist or statist. In sum, since both curves contradict Null Hypothesis 3 with high statistical significance, it must be rejected.
As with Hypotheses 1 and 2, there are several indirect tests that also can be made--these get more at the implications of the underlying theory and the sense of Hypothesis 3 than at its operational meaning.
If the
There is also the theoretical implication that violence between states will be higher the less they are libertarian, even relative to their overall conflict behavior. That is, nonlibertarian states should have higher violence even in proportion to their conflict behavior. If nonviolent conflict behavior and violence are separately cross-tabulated against the nation types, the
Earlier in this section, the curves of violence were found to fit Hypothesis 3. By theory, we should also expect a curvilinear regression to do equally well for the maximum conflict behavior, whether violent or not. By only specifying violence, Hypothesis 3 allows for the empirical possibility that it may well fit the maximum violence, when violence occurs. However, for many joint political freedom or freedom .scores there may not be any violence at all, and if this lack of violence is at the nonlibertarian end, it is contrary to theory. Accordingly, curves were fitted to the Maximum Conflict Scale Value (of Figure 1) per political freedom, or freedom, score. The results are shown in Figure 6 and Figure 7, where for comparability, the transformed scores are used for freedom (see Note 17). Their equations are:
- y = -26.2 + 23.2nx1
- R2 = .87 p <.5 x 10-11, one-tailed
y = -26.7 + 24.1nx2
- R2 = .83 p <.5 x 10-9, one-tailed
- where
- y = score on the Conflict Scale of Figure 1
- x1 =joint dyadic political freedom score
- x2 = joint dyadic freedom score
- n = natural logarithm
- N = 25
As should be expected, the maximum conflict behavior per political freedom or freedom score is well represented by continually rising curves, logarithmic in each case. This is shown by the coefficients of determination R2, both of which are highly significant. Freedom, however, is not a significantly better fit than political freedom. But when the results get this good (accounting for at least 83% of the variance), even greater significant improvement becomes very difficult.
Nonetheless, as theory predicts, when the curves of Figure 6 and Figure 7 are overlayed, as shown in Figure 5 the freedom curve is higher. That is, for the same political freedom and (transformed) freedom score, freedom predicts to a higher level of violence.
All this aside, the plots and shape of the curves in Figure 6 and Figure 7 in the region of those dyads involving libertarian states sum up the theory underlying Hypothesis 1 and Hypothesis 3. Clearly, freedom makes a critical difference in conflict behavior and marks a fundamental threshold between violence and nonviolence. Note especially that the greatest increase in the maximum conflict behavior along the curves happens when freedom is beginning to be lost, and the maximum violence occurs when both members of a dyad are no longer free at all.
Contiguity is not an intervening variable: Contiguous or not, libertarian states do not exert violence on each other; and whether having common borders or not, the less freedom in states, the more violence between them.
Whether libertarian is defined by political freedom or freedom, the data are highly supportive of the propositions. However, while economic freedom does not significantly detract from the Joint Freedom Proposition, it is clearly important for the Freedom one. To add economic freedom to civil liberties and political rights is to reduce significantly the level of violence for a state overall, or between particular states. For the Freedom Proposition, the libertarian's (or classical liberal's) faith in the peaceful effects of economic freedom appears" according to these data, well justified.
The best check against normative bias involves two stages. One is presenting clear and precise data and methods, using systematic and objective techniques, and making tests and conclusions intersubjectively verifiable. The second is even more important. It is the actual attempt to refute through reanalysis or new data what one believes to be biased or wrong. It is, in short, through the dialectical process of presenting controversial results and the attempts at their public refutation that we check bias.
(2) The sample is too limited, and does not include the period when democracies were heavily involved in war, such as the Suez or Vietnam War periods. First, in including all violence for five years, the sample is hardly limited. Second, other samples were drawn on, such as of all wars between 1816 and 1974, and all threats or actual use of force between 1945 and 1965, which all show the same lack of violence or wars between democracies. Third, such wars as Vietnam are irrelevant to the Joint Freedom Proposition, for that is a case of a libertarian state versus a nonlibertarian one. In any case, one must make one's tests with one sample at a time. The real question is whether this sample is important and these tests well done.
(3) Violence is misconstrued. This study severely neglects the violence of the rich or imperialist nations against the poor, or what is called "structural violence." "Violence" as physically attacking the life, limb, and property of others is the consensual meaning in both field and libertarian theory. This criticism would really want to use another theory and meaning, one based on a socialist and equalitarian perspective. Fine. But then the onus is the critic's to show that the concept of "structural violence" will yield better results, in some sense, than the one given here.
(4) The theory is too sketchy--its logic and properties need detailing, especially regarding economic freedom. I agree, but the purpose here is to test the two propositions and not to present the theory that I have elaborated elsewhere in greater detail (e.g., Vol. 4: War, Power, Peace).
With regard to economic freedom, the basic idea is that intervention of centralized, coercive power--government--into a social field has certain social effects, among which is an increase in the polarization of interests (forces) and a reduction of cross-pressures. By theory and holding other things constant, this should increase the level of violence in the social field (Vol. 2: The Conflict Helix: Part VIII) and decrease inhibitions in the foreign policy behavior of the elite. That mixed capitalist-socialist democratic systems like Sweden or Denmark, therefore, should be more violent than the United States or West Germany may strike some as silly. But then among the mixed democracies are also Israel, the United Kingdom, and Portugal; and also among the capitalist are Iceland, Switzerland, and New Zealand. For these two groups the claim that the former should and does have more violence is not at all strange. All this says, of course, is that the theory should not be left to socialist or liberal predispositions, but must be tested systematically. And this I have tried to do here.
(5) But you still should have carried out a sensitivity analysis. What would be the result if say, Sweden's freedom values were changed from partially free to free? Ordinarily, I think it methodologically unwise to change the values of a case alone in a sensitivity study, for then it is not clear what unique or common aspects of a case are causing the resulting effects. A better approach is to vary uniformly a variable or group of cases based on some theoretical or hypothetical principle. Here, I have in fact done this. For although mixed capitalist-socialist democracies like Sweden, Denmark, and Norway are coded partially libertarian on the freedom scale (and these are the cases that I believe will most bother some readers), their values are all changed to libertarian for the political freedom scale. That is, on the principle that political and civil rights completely dominate economic freedom, Sweden, Norway, and others are treated as free. Thus we have the two sets of results for political freedom and freedom, where those for political freedom in comparison to freedom can be considered methodologically a sensitivity analysis of the role of economic freedom.
(6) Contiguity should have been measured on a many-valued scale to take account of the impact of near contiguity. Perhaps, but I do not believe the scale will make much difference. Politically, the threshold condition is a common border; lack of such contiguity is, however scaled, of a different order. In other words, scaling contiguity should only marginally, if at all, alter the present results.
(7) Statistical tests were done without a well-defined sample, in a sample survey sense. The population is of interstate, dyadic violence, anywhere, anytime. The sample is of all such violence between 1976 and 1980 and was selected randomly with regard to the hypothesis. It is arguable whether this sample represents well the relevant characteristics of the historical population, but the working assumption is that it does.
Clearly, more samples must be taken and much more work be done before this question can be shelved; however, recall that other and larger samples of war and violence were used also.
But there is another answer. The statistical tests also assess whether for the given sample the particular combination of results (i.e., no violence falling among libertarian dyads) could occur by chance. And if the critic does not like my answer about sampling, he should nonetheless accept the statistical tests as valid on these second (not secondary) grounds.
(8) The variance in violence that libertarianism explains is low (see Figure 2 and Figure 3). Therefore, while the results are statistically significant, they are for practical purposes insignificant. True, the variance explained is low in some cases (but note also the high variance for the functions fitting the highest magnitudes of violence), but explaining variance is not the essence of this study. It is determining whether the prediction of no violence, or of decreasing violence with increasing libertarianism, holds true, and if so, whether this result could be due to chance. As to practical significance, the policy importance of establishing the credibility of these propositions should be obvious.
* Scanned from R.J. Rummel, "Libertarianism and International Violence," The Journal of Conflict Resolution 27 (March 1983): 27-71. I am indebted to Douglas Bond for his help in checking the data and calculations on the draft prior to publication. For this web site edition, typographical errors have been corrected, clarifications added, and style updated.1a.The conclusion of the five-volumes (Chapter 13 of Vol. 5: The Just Peace) is: "In total, some violence is inevitable; extreme violence and war are not. To eliminate war, to restrain violence, to nurture universal peace and justice, is to foster freedom."
1. The strongly supportive studies are Babst (1972), Rummel (Vol. 4: War, Power, Peace: Project 48), and Small and Singer (1976). Only these studies explicitly bear on the proposition. Also strongly, but indirectly (as inferences from descriptive analyses of many related variables), supportive are the overlapping studies by Rummel (Vol. 4: War, Power, Peace: Projects 10, 11, 12, and 13). Less strongly supportive, but still positive in that their results are what should be found were the proposition correct, are Vincent (1977a, 1977b, 1979) and Rummel (Vol. 4: War, Power, Peace: Project 7). Supportive, but indirectly so, are the studies of Barringer (1972) and the four independent studies of Rummel, (Vol. 4: War, Power, Peace: Projects 16, 30, 25 and 1). There is one ambiguous set of studies by Rummel (Vol. 4: War, Power, Peace: Projects 20, 21, and 32). No strongly negative studies exist, to my knowledge. One negative study is by Rummel (Vol. 4: War, Power, Peace: Project 43), and an indirectly negative one is also by him (Vol. 4: War, Power, Peace: Project 14). The only other negative study is by Phillips (1969), and it is indirectly relevant.
To review the discussion of the evidence with regard to the two propositions, see the Joint Freedom and Freedom Propositions in Vol. 4: War, Power, Peace.
2. Such as Israel's attack on the spy ship USS Liberty during the 1967 Arab-Israel War, killing 34 American sailors. Israel claimed this to be an error. There is also the question of whether Israel would be classified as a libertarian state in 1967, since by virtue of its limitations on political rights and civil liberties it was barely, if at all, politically free. Further considering its mixed capitalist-socialist economy should suffice to classify it as only partially free.
3. For the years 1976 to 1980, see Freedom at Issue, January-February, 1977, p. 9; January-February, 1978, p. 7; January-February, 1979, pp. 4-5; January-Ftbruary, 1980, pp. 4-5; January-February, 1981, pp. 4-5. Also beginning for 1978, Freedom House has published a Freedom in the World Yearbook, which presents the same ratings along with a brief description of the freedom in each state.
4. Freedom House's ratings are explicit, consistent across years, cover all states and territories, and most important, discriminate in regard to what I mean by libertarianism. To check its discrimination consider how Freedom House rates states whose freedom or nonfreedom is marginal or controversial. Israel, for example, is rated in 1978 a 2 for political rights and 2 for civil liberties, compared to 1-1 ratings for Austria, Denmark, and Iceland. Poland and Yugoslavia received 6-5, compared to 7-6 for the USSR, 6-6 for China, and 7-7 for Albania. Iran in 1977 is 6-5, changed to a 5-5 in 1980 after the revolution.
5. On the nature, reliability, and coding of event data, see Appendix II of Vol. 4: War, Power, Peace.
6. The dimensions are limited to official conflict, which best reflects the structural-institutional relationship between libertarianism and violence. The dimension of antiforeign demonstrations, which usually delineates the behavior of small, nonrepresentative private groups and individuals, is excluded thereby. For a survey of the quantitative literature on these dimensions, see Rummel (Vol. 4: War, Power, Peace: Chapter 15).
6a. Regarding the product moment, see my Understanding Correlation.
7. This probability shows that the means are too close together to be likely from independent random samples (p <.02). The explanation is that the Foreign Conflict Scale of Figure 1 squeezes out of the variable's scaling the chance deviation between coders, i.e., reduces the unreliability in the scaling technique and thus the difference in means.
7a. Especially note that the measure of violence used here is of intensity, not of the number of violent acts or wars. This is consistent with the theory, where the potential losses in foreign violence will interact with the other conditions (cross-pressures, norms, etc.) limiting or preventing the leaders of a libertarian state from escalating foreign conflict to the use of military violence.
8. "Current News" is prepared by the Current News Branch, Department of the Air Force, as executive agent for the Department of Defense.
9. This conversion involved the following. Let i and j be the actor and object in a directed dyad ij. Then for the symmetrical dyad i-j, the highest scale value for dyad ij or ji for each event-variable was taken as the scale value for the symmetrical dyad i-j.
10. For four classifications the degrees of freedom would usually be 3. However, the theory only stipulates the distribution of violence--two classifications--independently of the empirical data. Thus, 2 classifications - 1 = 1 d.f.
11. It is possible that libertarian dyads may have a much smaller (but nonzero) probability of violence than others, but still have violence, and thus violate Hypothesis 1. If, for example, there is really a one-in-a-million probability of violence (not the theoretical zero probability) for libertarian dyads, the zero violence for the 1976-1980 period would be a random result. (However, on the null hypothesis that the probability of P-P dyads having violence is one-half that of others, the zero violence is still significant at p <.032.). The test for this possibility requires generating across different time periods a number of samples like the ones here. In any case, all these tests are samples that should be considered as part of a process of building, or wrecking, our confidence in Hypothesis 1.
12. There are some errors and problems in the Small and Singer article. In their Table 6 the first t-test should be -.68, not -.76; in Table 6 the first t-test should be 1.05, not .68, and the second should be 2.84, not 1.45. The latter is then a significant result at p <.0023 (one-tailed, using the z distribution at 146 d.f.), not insignificant as Small and Singer claim. That is, democracies have significantly fewer killed in interstate wars, excluding the world wars. There is also a problem in their count of common borders (see Note 14).
13. These are a "rightward-drifting Finnish democracy joining Germany" in her attack on the USSR in 1941, and thus becoming technically at war with the democracies fighting Hitler, and "an ephemeral republican France attacking an ephemeral republican Rome in 1849" (Small and Singer, 1976: 67).
14. "In thirty-eight (76%) of our fifty interstate wars the belligerents shared common land boundaries; in five (another 10%) of the remaining twelve, they were neighbors through the proxy of colonial holdings" (Small and Singer, 1976: 67). These numbers, however, do not tally against their list of wars and participants. Apparently, Small and Singer really were referring to a geographic distance scale, and nations within a certain distance were considered contiguous. However, even then their numbers are not reproducible.
On behalf of Singer and his Correlations of War Project, I received the following revised calculations from Scott G. Gates: For all wars 25.8% of dyads had common borders; 41.3%, excluding the world wars; 58.5% also excluding the Korean and Austro-Prussian War. The number of wars in which a majority of dyads had a common border is 56%; it is 72% when the borders of colonial holdings also are included. Taking a slightly different slant, 68% of the wars were initiated by contiguous nations or the major participants were mostly contiguous; 80% if colonial holdings are included.
Clearly, these statistics weaken the Small and Singer argument. I wish to thank Scott G. Gates for providing a most detailed and helpful response to my questions to J. David Singer on the Small-Singer article.
14a. On the coefficient of determination, see "correlation squared" of Understanding Corrrelation.
15. The t-test of any differences a - b is t = (a - b)/D, where D is the sampling standard deviation of the differences. Then, t = (a - b)/ (S2
16. Since I am defining mathematical functions that may be useful in studies other than this one, rather than statistically testing contingencies I employed the full sample of dyadic violence used for testing Hypothesis 1.
17. The transformation was as follows. Freedom scores 6 and 7 were each given a new score of 4, 8 and 9, a new score of 5; 10 and 11, a new score of 6; ... ; 55 and 56, a new score of 28 (at the midpoint-to make up for an extra freedom score compared to political freedom-scores 30, 31, and 32 were each given a new score of 16). Then the highest violence score for 6 and 7 became that for the new score of 4; the highest for 8 and 9 became that for 5, and so on.
18. The reason for the difference in N is that no dyad having the political freedom scale value of 10 had violence (as can be seen from Figure 2).
19. I need to underline here that the classification of politically free or free states depends on Freedom House's criteria of "free," "partially free," and "nonfree" types, and therefore was established for this study prior and external to any data analysis.
20. 1 am well aware of the dichotomy between facts and values. However, values, often involve empirical assumptions that can be tested. On this dichotomy, see my Vol. 5: The Just Peace (Section 4.2.4E). See Part II of the book for my theory of social justice.
21. 1 have tried to deal normatively and systematically with the concept of structural violence elsewhere (Vol. 5: The Just Peace, Section 3.9.3).
BABST, D. V. (1972) "A force for peace." Industrial Research (April): 55-58.
BARRINGER, R. E. (1972) War: Patterns of Conflict. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
BUENO DE MESQUITA, B. (1981) The War Trap. New Haven, CT: Yale Univ. Press.
FEIERABEND, 1. K. and R. L. FEIERABEND (1973) "Violent consequences of violence," pp. 187-219 in H. Hirsch and D. C. Perry (eds.) Violence as Politics: A Series of Original Essays. New York: Harper & Row.
---. (1972) "Systematic conditions of political aggression: an application of frustration-aggression theory," pp. 136-183 in I. K. Feierabend, R. L. Feierabend, and T. R. Gurr (eds.) Anger, Violence, and Politics: Theories and Research. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
FERRIS, W. H. (1973) The Power Capabilities of Nation-States: International Conflict and War. Lexington, MA: D. C. Heath.
Freedom at Issue (1981) (January-Fcbruary).
GASTIL, R. D. (1981) Freedom in the World 1981. New York: Freedom House.
HOLSTI, K. J. (1966) "Resolving international conflicts: a taxonomy of behavior and some figures on procedures." J. of Conflict Resolution 10 (September): 272-296.
PHILLIPS, W. R. (1969) "Dynamic patterns of international conflict." Ph.D. dissertation, University of Hawaii, Honolulu.
PRIDE, R. A. (1970)"Origins of democracy: a cross-national study of mobilization, party systems, and democratic stability." Sage Professional Papers on Comparative Politics, Vol. 1, Series 01-012. Beverly Hills, CA: Sage.
RUMMEL, R.I. (1981) Vol. 5: The Just Peace. Beverly Hills, CA: Sage.
---. (1979) Vol. 4: War, Power, Peace. Beverly Hills, CA: Sage.
---. (1976) Vol. 2: The Conflict Helix. Beverly Hills, CA: Sage.
---. (1977) Field Theory Evolving. Beverly Hills, CA: Sage.
---. (1966) "A foreign conflict code sheet." World Politics 18, 283-2%.
(1963) "Dimensions of conflict behavior within and between nations," pp. 1-50 in General Systems Yearbook of the Society for General Systems Research, Vol. 8.
SINGER, J. D. (1972) The Wages of War: A Statistical Handbook. New York: John Wiley.
SMALL, M. and J. D. SINGER (1976) "The war-proneness of democratic regimes, 1816-1965." Jersulam J. of Int. Relations 1 (Summer): 50-69.
VINCENT, J. (1979) Project Theory: Interpretation and Policy Relevance. Washington, DC: University Press of America.
---. (1977a) "Distance theory: an inventory of significant findings for conflict." Attributes and National Behavior. Research Monograph 27. (unpublished)
---. (1977b) "Project theory: an overview and selected results." Presented to the Canadian School of Peace Research, Carleton University, Ottawa.
WRIGHT, L. M. (1982) "A survey of economic freedoms." Freedom At Issue (January-February): 15-20.
Go to top of document